Navigate
  • Home
  • Our Story
  • Categories
    • Articles
    • Book Reviews
    • Interviews
    • Live Discussions
    • Podcast
    • Talks
  • Topics
    • Apologetics
    • Epistemology
    • Free Stuff
    • God
    • Moral Argument
    • Naturalism
    • Reformed Epistemology
    • Science
    • Street Epistemology
    • Theology
  • Events
    • Conferences
      • CCv1 Conference
      • CCv2 Conference
    • Events
      • CC Exchange 2022
      • CC Exchange 2023
  • Shop
  • Free Resources
  • FAQ
  • Get in Touch
  • Testimonials
  • Donate?
  • Follow Us
    • Facebook
    • Twitter
    • SoundCloud
    • YouTube
Capturing Christianity
31K
15K
175K
16K
Capturing Christianity Capturing Christianity
  • Home
  • Our Story
  • Topics
    • Apologetics
    • EAAN
    • Epistemology
    • Faith
    • Interviews
    • Live Discussion
    • Moral Argument
    • Naturalism
    • Science
    • Street Epistemology
    • Theology
    • Reformed Epistemology
  • Events
    • Conferences
      • CCv1 Conference
      • CCv2 Conference
    • Events
      • CC Exchange 2022
      • CC Exchange 2023
  • Shop
  • Info
    • FAQ
    • Testimonials
  • Get in Touch
  • Donate
0
  • Articles

The Teleological Menace, Why Biology (Still) Requires God

  • December 11, 2021
  • 4 comments
  • 10 minute read
  • 3.4K views
  • Seth Hart
Total
20
Shares
20
0
0

In March of 2013, a lengthy article appeared in The Weekly Standard with the simple yet provocative title, “The Heretic.” The piece was accompanied by an ominous painting of a suited man, securely fastened to a stake above an encroaching fire. Encircling the ill-fated “heretic” are a horde of darkened, hooded figures. Some observe the execution with stoic reservation while others taunt the victim and revel at the violent spectacle.

The scene, which evokes cultural tropes of medieval inquisitions and their supposed anti-intellectualism, ironically depicts the academic barrage raised against famed atheist philosopher Thomas Nagel by his philosophical and scientific peers. According to the article, Nagel had been found guilty of the crime of challenging the reigning naturalistic paradigm, venturing even to publish his latest work, Mind and Cosmos, with the provocative subtitle Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False.[1] The work triggered a horde of scathing reviews from intellectuals like Steven Pinker, Daniel Dennett, and Jerry Coyne—the latter summarily dismissing Nagel as a mere “teleologist” and, consequently, “anti-science.”[2]

One might suppose from this salvo of academic rancor that the subject of teleology remains taboo in academic circles. Nothing could be further from the truth. In fact, nearly a decade prior, Mark Perlman declared teleology to be the “hottest topic in philosophy of biology, psychology and mind.”[3] Nagel’s crime, it seems, was to attribute to natural teleology anti-materialistic implications.[4] Nevertheless, Nagel dared to believe that, like the prodigal son, teleology might return home and once again be welcomed into scientific discourse. In this second part of this series, I look at this reemergence of teleology, particularly in modern philosophy of biology and the role of adaptations and proper functions. As will become clear, the whole field of biology rests on fundamentally teleological assumptions—a portentous omen against naturalism’s claim of scientific preeminence. Life, it seems, is irreducibly teleological, and it will take more than the metaphorical burning of heretics to prevent the increasing tide of teleological realism from breaking the shores of academic discourse.

A New Hope

As Étienne Gilson observed in 1984, “Rare are those mechanists who admit that there may be teleology in nature.”[5] Mark Perlman echoes this sentiment, stating, “By the twentieth century, analytic philosophers were positively allergic to any mention of teleology or teleological function.”[6] Many, even within academia, still live under this impression, yet statistics speak another story. The intellectual tides have shifted, and, by one now slightly dated count, the topic consumes 10-14% of the discussion in several major contemporary works from related fields.[7] For instance, Francisco Ayala, as early as 1970, argues, “Teleological explanations are appropriate and indispensable in biology, and… are fully compatible with causal accounts, although they cannot be reduced to nonteleological explanations without loss of explanatory content.”[8]

More recently, the famed work of Chilean biologists Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana lists autopoiesis as a clear manifestation of an organism’s teleological unity. Since the individual systems are dependent upon the unity of the network, the investigator must understand each system as operating toward a common end. In a cell, for instance, each system relies upon the other systems for the attainment of their goals. Unlike machines, each part receives its identity only in relation to the whole. Due to these implications, Varela himself has since become a teleological realist.[9] Finally, Michael Tkacz has argued persuasively that optimality modeling, the most common method of determining adaptations in modern biology, provides a “particularly clear and evocative examples [of] research programs in which final cause plays an explicit unifying role in explanation.”[10]

Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of teleology.

Georg Toepfer

The list could be compiled endlessly. For instance, David Oderberg has written extensively on why the concepts “organism” and “species” are, themselves, teleological since each one is defined by the unity preserved by essential, goal-oriented traits of creatures.[11] Georg Toepfer’s work has reached a nearly identical conclusion, leading to the provocative statement, “With this understanding of ‘teleology’ in mind, it becomes possible to modify Theodosius Dobzhansky’s famous dictum ‘nothing makes sense in biology except in the light of evolution’… to: ‘nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of teleology’.”[12] This summary fails to even touch on the work by Andreas Wagner, Denis Walsch, Michael Hanby, and innumerable other philosophers and biologists who all seem to be arriving at the same conclusion: life is goal-directed.

The Naturalists Strike Back

Unsurprisingly, naturalists have not been silent against this onslaught of support for teleological realism. These “teleonaturalists,”[13] as they have been called, have one common goal: demonstrate that biological teleology is nothing more than a useful fiction—a heuristic that can be dispensed with at any given time. Yet saying that one form of language is reducible to another is one thing; demonstrating this reduction is another entirely. There have been numerous attempts at just this sort of reduction (far more than can be covered in this short post), so I will limit myself to just two of the more prominent positions.

The most common stance by teleonaturalists has been labeled the etiological view, first proposed in analytic form independently by Ruth Millikan and Karen Neander.[14] The success of the theory in winning converts was so total, it was viewed as a rare instance of a “philosophical result.”[15] In short, the position maintains that a trait’s “proper function”[16] denotes nothing more than that trait’s contribution toward the survival of a reproductively established family. Thus, functionality derives from the historical role the feature has played in the evolutionary history of a group.

This seemingly commonsensical view has, however, sustained a volley of lethal hits. For instance, Plantinga crafts multiple thought experiments in which what is normally considered malfunctioning organs provide a reproductive advantage. For instance, in a culture where crippled individuals are the only ones who are sexually selected, we would not conclude that being crippled was the proper function of legs. Likewise, Plantinga imagines a tyrannical, Nazi-like figure assuming power and reprogramming all non-Aryan subjects with a genetic malformation. When these subjects attempt to open their eyes, they experience severe pain, leaving them unable to perform normal life functions. All non-Aryans not displaying this gene are then systematically wiped out. Having allowed for their survival, would severe pain then become the proper function of eyes?[17]

Robert Koons and Alexander Pruss have exercised similar logic in another direction. They imagine a world where all sick and dying creatures are taken by benevolent aliens to the “Great Grazing Ground” where they are revived and continue to thrive. In this world, no biological feature would have a proper function, since nothing would ever contribute to the survival of the organism. Wings would not have the function of flying since, no matter how well they operated, the organism bearing them would inevitably survive.[18]

Elsewhere, Pruss argues that functionality should not depend on something extrinsic to the organism. If, for instance, curious aliens (he seems to have a liking for extraterrestrial thought experiments) kidnap all colorblind individuals and the earth subsequently experiences a mass extinction of humans, colorblindness would suddenly become the function of eyes. Proper functionality, he argues, should not depend on events causally unrelated to the organism.[19] More objections have been raised by philosophers Jerry Fodor[20] and Denis Walsch, leading the latter to declare, “The Etiological Theory of Function is less a triumph of philosophical analysis than a victim of it.”[21]

Recognizing the shortcomings of the etiological perspective, John Bigelow and Robert Pargetter offered a revised account of biological functions which they call the “propensity theory.”[22] Functions, they claim, ought to explain survival rather than survival explaining functions. Thus, they instead propose that functions derive from a subjunctive property of the features in question.[23] If an attribute would confer survival value for a creature in its normal environment, the attribute can be said to function in that respect. In this way, the first arrival of the feature would have a function—a statement denied by the etiological perspective. Moreover, propensity theory would return to functions their explanatory power. Functions would account for the eventual survival of the feature. Thus, the propensity theory, they claim, avoids many of the pitfalls of the etiological view.

Bigelow and Pargetter are, however, open to possible objections to their offering. For instance, the proposal relies on the concept of a “normal” or “natural environment.”[24] This concept is notoriously difficult to define or determine for individual species. However, they assure the reader that “this sort of variable parameter is a common feature of many useful scientific concepts.”[25] Similarly, their proposal would lead to some counterintuitive conclusions. For instance, the function of hearts is to pump blood rather than to make audible thumping sounds, yet since the advent of advanced medical technology, these sounds can be used to detect abnormalities in the heart’s beating, thus conferring a survival advantage to the sound of heartbeats. One would have to conclude, then, that hearts can now be said to have two equal functions—pumping blood and making a thumping noise. Waving off these objections, they argue the justification for propensity theory outweighs the force of these counterexamples.[26]

However, this second teleonaturalistic offering has its own brand of issues. Many of the thought experiments leveled against the etiological perspective would work equally well against the propensity theory. Another point of attack has been the aforementioned notion of “natural habitat.” If the propensity theory relies on a stable notion of a creature’s habitat, then it is sneaking historical factors into the model. A trait’s current context may not, in fact, be the “natural” habitat from which the trait arose. As Perlman notes, “Without a historical basis, it is hard to distinguish between cases where a trait is survival-enhancing yet now fatal in an unnatural habitat, or naturally lethal in a natural habitat.”[27] Hence, the propensity offering has not truly cleansed itself of historical considerations. This would, perhaps, be a survivable objection. However, Koons and Pruss have added that the concept of a “normal environment” in Bigelow and Pargetter’s paper is viciously circular.[28] A “normal environment” is defined as the location where the species’ organs function properly, yet, simultaneously, we are told proper functionality is defined by the creature’s normal habitat.

Moreover, Plantinga has added that, on occasion, a dysfunctional organ might aid in survival. If, for instance, a major artery was to have elastic holes in it, then a properly beating heart would lead to hemorrhaging and death. However, a heart that beats at a considerably slower rate would, in fact, allow the individual to survive.[29] Foreseeing this objection, Bigelow and Pargetter briefly note that the definition of a “normal habitat” should be extended to include the normal bodily functions of the organism.[30] While this reply cuts off one objection, it simultaneously creates another. Reparative systems, such as blood clotting, only function properly when bodily conditions are abnormal. Hence, these systems would, on this account, have no proper function.[31]

The Return of the Theistic Argument?

These are only two of the more prominent theories currently on offer, yet the prospects for other, lesser-known alternatives looks equally bleak. Plantinga has therefore concluded, “The prospects for a naturalistic account of proper function look dim.”[32] But what does all of this have to do with theism and atheism? Could not the intellectually honest atheist simply admit that lifeforms are teleological without committing herself to any further consequence? Ayala himself has made this claim, stating that one could adopt an Aristotelian approach, whereby teleology is regarded as immanent within creatures only. He writes, “According to Aristotle there is no intelligent maker of the world. The ends of things are not consciously intended.”[33]

While Ayala must be commended for his biology, his philosophy is lacking at this point. While Ayala is certainly correct that Aristotle did not posit a “designer”, his teleological system nevertheless is grounded upon the Prime Mover (Aristotle’s “god”) as the principle of perfection that all creatures seek to imitate. Thus, any appeal to a supposed “Aristotelian” teleology fails to break free of theistic implications. In fact, it is difficult to discover any coherent teleological system that is not fundamentally grounded on theism. Even the aforementioned Nagel has been criticized for his failure to even engage Scholastic and Ancient accounts of teleology and their criticisms of a purely immanent teleology—ones that mirror his own offering.[34]

All in all, it remains to be seen if it is even possible to account for teleology outside of a theistic foundation. Obviously, much more can be said in support of this, but given the length of this post so far, that will have to wait for another day. Nevertheless, it is fairly safe to conclude from this that if biology is truly teleological (as it seems it must be), theism appears to be the only coherent philosophical account of this feature currently on offer.

Footnotes

[1] Thomas Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).

[2] Michael Chorost, “Where Thomas Nagel Went Wrong,” The Chronicle of Higher Education, May 13, 2013, https://www.chronicle.com/article/Where-Thomas-Nagel-Went-Wrong/139129 (accessed 8 May 2019).

[3] Mark Perlman, “The Modern Philosophical Resurrection of Teleology,” The Monist 87 (2004), 46.

[4] See Simon Oliver, Review of Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False, Studies in Christian Ethics 27(4): 508-10.

[5] Étienne Gilson, From Aristotle to Darwin and Back Again, trans. by John Lyon (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), 105.

[6] Perlman, “Modern,” 4.

[7] Ernst Mayr, “The Idea of Teleology,” Journal of the History of Ideas 53 (1992), 117, citing the work of Morton Beckner, Alexander Rosenberg, Michael Ruse, and Rolf Sattler.

[8] Francisco J. Ayala, “Teleological Explanations in Evolutionary Biology,” Philosophy of Science 37:1 (March 1970), 8.

[9] Simon Oliver, “Teleology Revived? Cooperation and the Ends of Nature,” Studies in Christian Ethics 26:2 (2013), 164.

[10] Michael W. Tkacz, “Thomistic Reflections on Teleology and Contemporary Biological Research,” New Blackfriars 94:1054 (Nov. 2013), 657.

[11] See David Oderberg, Real Essentialism (Oxford: Routledge Publishing, 2009).

[12] Georg Toepfer, “Teleology and its Constitutive Role for Biology as the Science of Organized Systems in Nature,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (2012), 115.

[13] Colin Allen and Jacob Neal, “Teleological Notions in Biology,” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2019 edition. Ed. Edward N. Zalta, accessed April 5, 2019, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/teleology-biology/.

[14] Ruth Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); Karen Neander, “The Teleological Notion of ‘Function,’” Australian Journal of Philosophy 69:4 (1991): 454-468.

[15] Denis Walsh, “Function and Teleology,” in Evolutionary Biology: Conceptual, Ethical, and Religious Issues, ed. R. Paul Thompson and Denis M. Walsh (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 195. Emphasis mine.

[16] Millikan uses this term in a “technical sense” and seeks to differentiate it from more common uses of the term “function.” This distinction, however, will not affect my analysis.

[17] See Alvin Plantinga, Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 204.

[18] Robert C. Koons and Alexander Pruss, “Must Functionalists Be Aristotelians?” in Causal Powers, ed. Jonathan D. Jacobs (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 203.

[19] Illustration derived (and slightly modified) from Alexander Pruss, “From Human Nature to God,” Lecture, Oriel College, University of Oxford, 23 May 2019.

[20] J. A. Fodor, A Theory of Content and Other Essays, vol 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), 71ff.

[21] Denis Walsch, “Function and Teleology,” in Evolutionary Biology: Conceptual, Ethical, and Religious Issues, ed. R. Paul Thompson and Denis M. Walsh (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 195.

[22] John Bigelow and Robert Pargetter. “Functions,” The Journal of Philosophy 84:4 (Apr. 1987), 181-96.

[23] Ibid, 190-2.

[24] Ibid, 192.

[25] Ibid.

[26] Ibid, 196.

[27] Perlman, “Modern,” 21. Perlman credits this objection to Karen Neander and Peter Godfrey-Smith. I have not, unfortunately, been able to locate where they have separately offered this objection.

[28] Koons and Pruss, “Functionalists,” 201. Plantinga, Warrant, 206 has made a similar argument.

[29] Plantinga, Warrant, 206.

[30] Bigelow and Pargetter, “Functions,” 192.

[31] Ibid, 207.

[32] Plantinga, Warrant, 209.

[33] Ayala, “Teleological,” 14-5.

[34] Oliver, “Mind”, 510.

Total
20
Shares
Share 20
Tweet 0
Pin it 0
Seth Hart

Seth Hart is a PhD student in science and theology at the University of Durham. He holds masters in theology from Oxford, Regent College, and Johnson University. His current research delves into whether the field of biology and its fundamental concepts are built upon theistic foundations, arguing that terms like “adaptation”, “organism”, and “fitness” all entail the existence of God. He currently resides in Fayetteville, Arkansas with his wife and corgi.

SUBSCRIBE. BE AWESOME.

Get updates on new posts, upcoming live discussions, and more.

You May Also Like
View Post
  • Articles

CCv2 Apologetics Conference

  • Cameron Bertuzzi
  • June 8, 2022
View Post
  • Articles

CC Exchange 2022

  • Cameron Bertuzzi
  • February 7, 2022
View Post
  • Articles

Is Animal Suffering a Bigger Problem for Theists?

  • Seth Hart
  • February 3, 2022
Hummingbird
View Post
  • Articles

Btw, Evolution is Teleological

  • Seth Hart
  • November 23, 2021
View Post
  • Articles

The Gospels are Bíoi – So What? Three Lessons for Reading Them Well

  • John Nelson
  • October 26, 2021
View Post
  • Articles

Did American Christians Wage War on Darwin? (Spoiler Alert: No)

  • Seth Hart
  • October 11, 2021
View Post
  • Articles

Christianity’s War on Darwinism, or the War that Never Happened

  • Seth Hart
  • October 5, 2021
israel
View Post
  • Articles

Dr. Loke’s Closing Statement vs. Paulogia

  • Andrew Loke
  • August 31, 2021
Subscribe
Notify of
guest

guest

4 Comments
Oldest
Newest Most Voted
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
Brute Facts Podcast
Brute Facts Podcast
1 year ago

Wow. I haven’t ventured much into Philosophy of Biology and didn’t realize the complexity of argumentation in biological study. While teleology in biology seemed prima facie true, I haven’t been a fan of arguing for it, however admittedly unaware of the contemporary discussion and controversy involved. Well written and articulated article.

0
Reply
Matthew
Matthew
1 year ago

I very much enjoyed this article. I appreciate that the author details various accounts and their prominent challenges. If the author doesn’t mind, I have a few questions. First, what do you mean by “telos”? (It seems that you mean proper function.) Second, how does an organ’s proper function relate to its natural function? Are they identical? Third, how does an organ’s proper function relate to its goal or purpose? Are they identical? Fourth, how would you assess the following two accounts? (1) A natural function is any naturally selected behavior. This account doesn’t invoke goals or purposes. In this… Read more »

0
Reply
Seth Hart
Seth Hart
1 year ago
Reply to  Matthew

Hey Matthew! Thanks for the good questions. Here are some brief responses: (1) Telos is obviously just the Greek word for “end” or “purpose”. I use it here because of the philosophical “load” the term carries with it. “Proper function” is a term denoting that certain features have “design plans” (Plantinga’s words) or ways in which they are suppose to function. While the nuances in which Plantinga and others use the term differ slightly from how telos is used, the overall point is similar (namely, that there is a normative aspect to biological traits apparently absent from the other natural… Read more »

0
Reply
guy
guy
10 months ago

if a robot that can reproduce needs design then also a penguin, which is basically an organic robot which can reproduce.

0
Reply
about
Free 60-page eBook!
Join our super cool email list to receive a copy of our free 60-page eBook (and other cool stuff). Btw, Christianity is true.
Subscribe!
Support
If you find value in our content, prayerfully consider supporting us monthly on Patreon!
Follow Us!
Facebook 31K
Twitter 15K
YouTube 175K
Instagram 16K
#100plusargsforgod 606 118
The REAL reason I always look angry 😠😂 209 14
#reason #logic #science #blessed🙏 380 20
Guess what I’m doing this week? Btw, there’s still time to audit Dr. Craig’s class on the Trinity. Apparently, ALL of the material is new! And if you join late, you’ll still get access to the over 12 hours of lectures. 289 16
Btw, tonight is the night you can hang out with Cam and other CC supporters for 2+ hours discussing apologetics, philosophy, gaming, and whatever else comes up! 48 2
Quick Asbury update: I was able to record 2 interviews during my short trip to Asbury University over the weekend. The first interview was with Lena Marlowe. She's a senior at Asbury and was on the Gospel Choir during the service that launched the revival. I'm hoping to have her interview up today or tomorrow. 468 66
Capturing Christianity
  • Home
  • Free Stuff
  • FAQ
  • Testimonials
  • Contact
  • Donate?

Input your search keywords and press Enter.

wpDiscuz